Sunday, January 1, 2017

Judiciary and the Dilemma of ‘Office of profit’: A Pandora’s Box




M Jashim Ali Chowdhury
Published in: The Chittagong University Journal of Law, Vol. XI, 2006 (Published in March 2010 at pp 58 - 82.




Introduction

Though the expression ‘Office of Profit’ is not defined in the Constitution, it has a pretty sound backing of the doctrine of Separation of Power. The view is that holding executive offices by an MP or a Judge may either be incompatible with his duty or may affect his independence and thus weakens the loyalty to his assigned office. Then instead of ensuring the necessary accountability of the Executive, his office may become subservient to rather than the watchdog of the Executive.


The prohibition against any Member of Parliament taking any ‘office of profit’ was in the Constitution of Bangladesh, 1972 in sub-clause (f) of Article 66(2). This was however, renumbered as sub-clause (dd) by the Second Proclamation Order IV of 1978. The motive was to prevent any scope of timidity on the part of the Legislature to hold the Executive accountable. However, since the very nature of the Multi-Party Parliamentary Democracy makes the Executive more a part than a counterpart of the Legislature, the Constitution excludes some specific offices from the definition of office of profit in Article 66(2A). The Judiciary, on the other hand, is a completely different arena. Independence of judiciary requires it be secured that judges are so placed that during their term of office they remain above inducement or hope for preferment. A judge must be a recluse, a man apart.1 Accordingly Articles 147(3) and 99 were included in the Constitution of Bangladesh disqualifying the Supreme Court judges from holding ‘any office or post’ whatsoever both during the continuance of their service and after the retirement or removal therefrom. This two tier prohibition was intended to immune the judges from all sorts of allurement for possible future gains.



Unfortunately, Article 99 was amended later on to put a ceiling on the bar limiting it to any ‘office of profit’ in the service of the Republic other than ‘judicial or quasi-judicial’ offices. This indiscriminate insertion of ‘office of profit threshold’, widely used around the world in relation to the Members of Parliament, opened a Pandora’s box of political favoritism for the Judges. By now we have had many shocking instances of judges holding constitutional, judicial (e.g, Labor Appellate Tribunal, Administrative Tribunal etc), quasi-judicial or even non judicial offices like the Chief Election Commissioner (CEC), Chairman of the Anti-Corruption Commission and Chairman of the Law Commission under the guise of quasi-judicial office. Now-a-days Judges are seen to be rewarded not only after their retirement but also even during their service in the Supreme Court, appointment of Justice M. A. Aziz as CEC being the glaring example.


This write-up aims at surfing through the historical evolution of ‘office of profit’ to show how a concept essentially used in relation to the Legislature got a firm root in our judicial discourse. It strongly argues that applying the ‘office of profit threshold’ for the Judges needs a careful perusal and second thought. The later part of the paper explores the different standings of the Supreme Court over the past years to find out the genuine connotation of ‘office of profit in the service of the Republic’. Lastly, I come to a conclusion with some concrete what-to-do findings in this regard.



President’s ‘Lockean’ Prerogative of Mercy: A Lawful Lawlessness?




M. Jashim Ali Chowdhury

Published in: The Chittagong University Journal of Law
Vol XV (2010; published in May 2012), at pp 23-49





The right to pardon a criminal, either by mitigating or by entirely remitting the punishment, is certainly the most slippery of all the rights of the sovereign. By exercising it he can demonstrate the splendor of his majesty and yet thereby wreak injustice to a high degree. With respect to a crime of one subject against another, he absolutely cannot exercise this right, for in such cases exemption from punishment constitutes the greatest injustice toward his subjects.
Immanuel Kant
The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, John Ladd (trans.), Hackett, 2nd ed. 1999, p. 144


A legally sanctioned Alegality

The traditional understanding of Athenian, Roman and British jurists, among others, stands that a polity must make some provisions for the power to pardon, whether for the purpose of remedying injustice, tempering justice with mercy or furthering the interests of the state.[1] Ideally the power of pardon does not exist under a perfect administration of the laws. The admission of the power is a tacitly conceded imperfection of human action in the punishment of offenders. Yet some vilifies the concept for making a mockery of murder victims, undermining democracy, using raw power to cut down the law itself and making law meaningless. Some others reject such a feeling saying that clemency issues from a court of equity exercising a ‘prerogative’ inherent in the sovereign. The essence of a ‘prerogative’ being discretionary, its efficacy is bound up to its very disregard of declared law. Thus Jhon Locke famously defines ‘prerogative’ as:
[The] power to act according to discretion, for the public good, without the prescription of the Law, and sometimes even against it, is that which is called Prerogative. For since in some Governments the Law-making Power is not always in being, and is usually too numerous, and so too slow, for the dispatch requisite to Execution: and because also it is impossible to foresee, and so by laws to provide for, all Accidents and Necessities, that may concern the public; or to make such Laws, as will do no harm, if they are Executed with an inflexible rigor, on all occasions, and upon all Persons, that may come in their way, therefore there is a latitude left to the Executive power, to do many things of choice, which the Laws do not prescribe.[2]
However it is the insinuation of this ‘Lockean prerogative’[3], understood as a residuum of plenary executive power, independent of the specific grants of presidential power in the Constitution that has made most pardon exercises controversial and open to questions. Interestingly Article 49 of the Constitution of Bangladesh itself leaves no residuum regarding prerogative of mercy. Rather it provides a sweeping, unlimited and absolute authority in the President regarding the pardon power: 
The President shall have power to grant pardons,[4] reprieves[5] and respites[6] and to remit[7], suspend or commute[8] any sentence passed by any court, tribunal or other authority.



Moreover Sections 401[9], 402[10] and 402A[11] of the Code of Criminal Procedure 1898 add to the abundancy of the executive authority by empowering the head of the Executive, i.e., the Prime Minister as well in this regard. Predictably this absolute power carries with it an inherent danger of being abused and actually the case is so. In Bangladesh we had to bear the pain of seeing pardon of even death sentence only on political considerations.[12]

The abuse of discretion, however, is not a peculiar one for Bangladesh. More or less the controversial incidents of pardon are frequent in almost all parts of the world. Even in the USA[13], the most sophisticated democracy of the world, a series of high-profile pardons like Andrew Johnson’s sweeping pardons of thousands of former Confederate officials and military personnel after the American civil war, Gerald Ford's post-Watergate pardon of Richard Nixon,[14] Jimmy Carter’s grant of amnesty to Vietnam-era draft evaders, George H.W. Bush’s pardons of 75 people, including six Reagan administration officials accused in connection with the Iran-contra affair and Bill Clinton's eleventh-hour pardons of Marc Rich as well as other individuals[15] raised significant concerns about ways in which pardons might be used to advance personal, partisan or pecuniary interests.

Therefore several scholars have put forth a variety of proposals, such as requiring that pardons be approved by a board; that president gives adequate notice to relevant parties before granting a pardon; that he gives reasons for the pardons; that pardons be issued only after conviction, or that legislature be empowered to disapprove of presidential pardons, etc.

This exercise shall try to explore the ins and outs of each potential alternative and examine their comparative adaptability in different jurisdictions, which may ultimately lead us to one, two or even more concrete ‘what to do’ findings suitable to the genius of the body politic we have got in Bangladesh. Even before that I would like to present a brief historic account of the pardon power as it was and is exercised by the British Crown. Keeping our common law heritage in mind it will help us to understand the breadth of the ‘prerogative’ that actually prevails in the homeland of common law jurisprudence. Inspiration is also heavily drawn from the American jurisprudence on presidential pardon.



Notes -- 

[1] John Dinan, The Pardon Power and the American State Constitutional Tradition, The Polity, Vol. 35, No. 3 (Apr., 2003), pp. 389-418, Palgrave Macmillan Journals, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3235525, (Accessed on: 25/07/2011), p. 408
[2] Jhon Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Section 160 of the Second Treatise) quoted in Thomas S. Langston and Michael E. Lind, John Locke & the Limits of Presidential Prerogative, The Polity, Vol. 24, No. 1 (Autumn, 1991), Palgrave Macmillan Journals, pp. 49-68 at p. 55; Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3234984 (Accessed on: 09/09/2011)
[3] Relying principally on a broad reading of the vesting clause of Article II, Section 1, of the U.S. Constitution, scholars, executive branch legal counsel, certain Supreme Court Justices and several Presidents of USA have claimed an essentially monarchical prerogative power for the American executive. These "presidentialists" frequently assert that the Framers and ratifiers of the U.S. Constitution intended to endow the President with a supposed "Lockean prerogative," understood as a residuum of plenary executive power, independent of the specific grants of presidential power in Article II. According to many presidentialists, Congress cannot restrict or eliminate this residual "executive prerogative" by law.
[4] Complete relinquishment of all sorts of punishments, sentences and legal disqualifications so as to restitute the convicted in the position he held before the conviction.
[5] Temporary suspension of operation of a conviction
[6] Postponement of execution of a sentence
[7] Reduction of amount of sentences without changing its nature, e.g., a longer version imprisonment may be converted into a shorter version imprisonment.
[8] Sanctioning a punishment lighter than the earlier one, e.g., simple imprisonment may be substituted in place of a rigorous imprisonment.
[9] When any person has been sentenced to punishment for an offence, the government may at any time without conditions or upon any conditions which the person sentenced accepts, suspend the execution of his sentence or remit whole or any part of the sentence.
[10] The government may, even without the consent of the person sentenced, commute any one of the following sentences for any other mentioned after it, death, transportation, rigorous imprisonment for a term not exceeding that to which he might have been sentenced, simple imprisonment for a like term, and fine.
[11] In case of death sentence, the powers granted in Sections 401, 402 maybe excercised by the President as well.
[12] Professor Dr. Iaj Uddi Ahmed pardoned the death penalty of Mr. Mohidduin Zinto, a worker of Sweden BNP, who was convicted to death in a murder case while others convicted for the same offence were executed. President Zillur Rahman also has pardoned at least twice on considerations which apparently seem to be purely partisan.
[13] The President's power to pardon is stated simply in the US Constitution: The President "shall have Power to grant Reprieves and Pardons for Offences against the United States, except in Cases of Impeachment" (Art. II, Sec 2 Cl. I of the Constitution of United States of America)
[14] Pardon was granted by President Gerald Ford to former President Richard Nixon on September 8, 1974, for official misconduct which gave rise to the Watergate Scandal. The majority of Americans showed disapproval and he was narrowly defeated in the Presidential campaign, two years later.
[15]Those receiving pardons included President Clinton’s brother, the son of his education secretary, his former housing secretary, Susan McDougal of Whitewater fame, an old political friend from Georgia, and Marc Rich, whom the government had indicted for the largest tax scam in the nation's history. Marc Rich fled the US to escape a massive tax invasion to Switzerland in 1983. Many present and former high ranking officials in Israel, as well as leaders of the Jewish community in America and Europe, urged the pardon of Rich because of his charitable contribution and services to Israeli causes, the peace process in the Middle East through education and health programs in Gaza and the West Bank. It was suggested that Rich’s wife, Denis made political contributions which comprise more than $1 million to the Democratic Party; $450000 to the Clinton library etc.



Contempt of Court: In Search of a "Law"






M. Jashim Ali Chowdhury*

Published in: The Chittagong University Journal of Law Vol. XVII, 2012 (p.24- 51)
The full text of the article is available at: 



Abstract
The seriousness and frequency in the recent attention of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh on its Contempt Jurisdiction has drawn a substantial public gaze. Here, the overall instability in the body politic over contentious constitutional and political issues has not left the judiciary untouched. Faced with the problems of choosing between what is right and what is easy, the highest judiciary of Bangladesh had unavoidably and unintentionally to be engaged in a bit of political discourse and hence became subject to both bona fide criticisms and motivated attacks from the vested quarters. Therefore, on many a occasion the Supreme Court ventured the path of punishing its contempt and paved the way for a heated debate on this.
The problems that the age old Contempt Act 1926 poses today are primarily two-fold. Firstly, this Act leaving an undefined offence of contempt with a maximum but nominal punishment creates an unwelcome vacuum, uncertainty and inadequacy in contempt jurisprudence. Secondly, the reactionary approach of ‘enforcing’ obedience through contempt power taken by the colonial judges has had a subtle but permanent impression in the mind set-up of the present day courts and judges. While the rest her South Asian neighbors have introduced important changes in contempt laws, the Bangladeshi jurisprudence on the Contempt of Court unfortunately still lives in the era of 1926. Though a Bill on Contempt of Court was tabled in the Parliament in 2006 it was not ultimately passed. A 2008 Ordinance made by the Military backed Caretaker Government was rejected outright by the Supreme Court. Therefore, we need a ‘Law’ capable of handling the problems of the 21st century with an approach suitable to the genius of the time.
In this paper I would present a short picture of the existing judge made, statutory and subordinate laws relating to contempt of courts in Bangladesh. The possible roadblocks that the High Court Division has put through The Contempt of Court Ordinance Case of 2008 on the way to the proposed rejuvenation are also addressed. Thereafter attention is paid to the emerging trends of contempt laws of Britain and also of our neighboring South Asian Countries. Thereafter I shall try to chalk out the guiding principles of the proposed Contempt Law for Bangladesh.


*  Assistant Professor, Department of Law, University of Chittagong





অতিরিক্ত বিচারপতিদের স্থায়ীকরণ প্রসঙ্গে মহামান্য আপিল বিভাগের সাম্প্রতিক রায়: একটি প্রাথমিক মূল্যায়ন ল'ইয়ার্স ক্লাব বাংলাদেশ সাক্ষাৎকার ...