Law as Politics:
Reflections on the Critical LegalStudies Movement
M
Jashim Ali Chowdhury
Assistant
Professor, Department of law, University of Chittagong
SCLS Law Review Vol. 1. No.2 [May 2018] p 17-21
Available Online: http://sclsbd.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/08/7.-Jashim-Ali-Chy-Law-as-Politics.pdf
Available Online: http://sclsbd.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/08/7.-Jashim-Ali-Chy-Law-as-Politics.pdf
Introduction
Critical Legal Studies
(hereinafter CLS) movement of the U.S. marked the combination of a legal way of
thought and a social network of left leaning legal scholars of 1970s. Though
loosely constructed as a legal theory, CLS lacks the ingredients necessary for
a full pledged legal theory. It is rather better described as a network of
like-minded legal scholars at Harvard and a way of legal thought.[1]
Prominent among the scholars were Roberto Unger, Duncan
Kennedy, David Kennedy, Morton Horwitz, Jack
Balkin, Mark Tushnet
and Louis Michael Seidman. As is put by Roberto Unger, though CLS was
meant to be “continued
as an organizing force only until the late 1980s,…its founders never meant it
to become an ongoing school of thought or genre of writing.”[2] Yet the movement became a very powerful
school of thought popularised
throughout America and the rest of the world. CLS has been perceived both as a
reaction to legal Formalism and Realism and a distinct theory of law.
CLS as a Reaction to Legal Formalism and Realism
CLS
movement started at the behest of some scholars inspired by the civil rights
movement (primarily black rights), feminist movements, opposition to Vietnam war
and concerns over rapid wealth disparity between the rich and the poor. The
movement questioned the traditional American understanding of law and legal
system. More specifically, it questioned the dominant trends of legal formalism
and legal realism.
Legal
Formalism
Legal
formalism was American middle ground in the naturalist and positivist
jurisprudence. Naturalists claim the laws to be emanating from moral and
natural sources. Positivists, on the other hand, claim the law to be deriving
from amoral and worldly authorities like the sovereign, executive and
legislature, etc. American formalist philosophy, in its turn, focused on a
different actor – the judiciary. Inspired by the principle of judicial review
established in Marbury v Madison 5
U.S. 137
(1803) the legal formalists claim
that law is what the judges say.
Basic
principles of legal formalism may be summed up as follows:
1)
Legal rules reside above other social and
political institutions. Once the lawmakers give us the rules, judges would
apply them to the facts of a case. Now the question is about the pile of
principles from which the rules would be found. Rules can be found from handful of general
principles containing some abstract concepts – such as, contract without
consideration is invalid, no guilt in absence of guilty mind, etc. There will
be a “mass of lower rules” deriving from these basic concepts. This tenet of
legal formalism is known as Conceptualism.[3]
2)
In applying the rule, the judges will not
consider other social interests or public policies that may seem relevant for
the case in hand. In this sense, the judge would simply apply the laws without
considering whether the outcome of the application is just and moral.[4] This concept is known as amorality
of adjudication.
3)
What the judge need
is simply the fact and a law. While there may be a huge lot of principles, the
judges would look for the one which is clear and straight forward in the area
and which is readily discoverable by the lawyers practicing in the area. This
is called restriction or denial of
choice.[5]In this sense, legal formalism aims at restricting the
judge’s discretion and hence it is also called the mechanical jurisprudence. One of the famous supporters of Legal
Formalism was Justice Antonin Scalia of the U.S. Supreme Court. In one of his
essay, A Matter of Interpretation, Scalia defended
textualism and formalism by claiming:
Of all the criticisms levelled
against textualism, the most mindless is that it is formalist. The answer to
that is, of course it's formalistic! The rule of law is about form
. . . A murderer has been caught with blood on his hands, bending over the body
of his victim; a neighbour with a video camera has filmed the crime and the
murderer has confessed in writing and on videotape. We nonetheless insist that
before the state can punish this miscreant, it must conduct a full-dress
criminal trial that results in a verdict of guilty. Is that not formalism? Long
live formalism! It is what makes us a government of laws and not of men.[6]
4)
Since the judges decide cases on the basis of distinctly
legal rules and reasons, the legal formalists claim that there is only one
right answer for every legal dispute. The judges will have to find that right
answer by survey of available precedents and sources. This one-right-answer justifying
one unique result is known as rule
determinacy.[7] One of
the famous critique of this one-right-answer
doctrine is Professor Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin believes that law may give more than one right answer in a given case if the
answer is attempted by different persons. Even if different judge may give the
same right answer, their reasoning may vary. So more-than-one right answer is
possible in every given case.[8]
Legal Realism
Dworkin’s
rejection of the formalist concept of rule
determinacy brings us to the Legal Realism evolved during the 1930s. If
Legal Formalism is a thesis, Legal Realism is an anti-thesis. Justice Oliver
Wendel Holmes J. of the U.S. Supreme Court is given the honour of the Founder
of American Legal Realism. In 1897, Justice Holmes delivered a famous speech
“The Path of Law” before the Boston University School of Law. Emphasising the
law-in-action over the law-in-books, Justice Holmes told: "The life of
the law has not been logic, it has been experience."[9]
Holmes believed that law is not all about some determinate rules rather it is some
prediction a legally interested
person might need to do in planning his legal actions. Holmes explains through
his famous “bad-man” example. Before deciding any course of action, a typical
bad-man would calculate all possible consequences which may follow his action.
At the end he would take only that route in which risks are the least and
profits are more. Like a bad-man, a lawyer preparing his case for a client
would calculate which judge would take which line of view. On that basis, the
lawyer would decide which law to be relied, which arguments to be made before
which judge. This is what is called Legal Realism- the law-in-action. Justice
Homes says:
But if we take the view of our friend - the bad man, we shall find that
he does not care two straws for the axioms or deductions, but that he does want
to know what the Massachusetts or English courts are likely to do in fact. I am
much of this mind. The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and
nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law.[10]
Basic
contours of legal realism may be summer up as follows:
1)
As a theory, legal realism is different from both
naturalism and positivism. Realists are not naturalists because, they don’t
accept the moral social values as something divine. They would rather see those
as products of historical and sociological facts which need be addressed from a
sociological and practical point of view. Reference to divinity is unnecessary.
Realists are also different from positivists in the sense that they refuse to
confine their investigations to state law and/or positive law only.
2)
Realists are different from formalists in the
sense that “what judges actually do in deciding cases, rather
than on what they say they are doing.”[11] Judges adjudicate more than they mechanically apply legal rules to some “uncontroversial fact-finding”. We
may never be sure that the facts and law identified in a judgment are the actual basis of
the decision that comes out. Realists claim that the legal rules and principles
elaborated in a judgment may hide some controversial political and moral
choices the judge may rear in his or her mind. In this sense, the rule
determinacy theory proposed by the legal formalists is not right. Statutory and case laws are indeterminate, and decisions of the judges are not based entirely
upon rule of law. This realist
perception is widely known as rule scepticism.[12]
CLS as a Distinct Theory of Law
From a
theoretical point of view, CLS questioned the precedent based common law norms
and its traditional inability or inertia to address the power bias of law. Critical
legal thinkers attempted to unveil the subtle partiality of the apparently
impartial and rigid legal doctrines, hidden interests and class domination
behind legal institutions and politics of laws.
Basic contours
of CLS may be summed up as follows:[13]
1)
The foremost assertion of CLS is, “Law is
Politics”. Legal reasoning is not different from political reasoning. Like
political ones, legal disputes are solved through a hazy combination of
coercion and reasoning. It is not pure reasoning at any rate.
2)
All imaginable legal questions are indeterminate.
Any well-developed legal system would permit the lawyers and judges to explore
principles and rules both within and across the system. Within the system, a contract
lawyer, for example, may rely on the dominant concept of agreement to establish
a right, subordinate concept of mistake and fraud to destroy a right. If he seeks
a bit different result, he may attack the concept of contract itself by
resorting to some socio-political principle based arguments. The rules being
indeterminate, the actors find themselves in a position of choice.
3)
Legal system is titled in favour of the
powerful persons and elites. The “haves” would dominate the institution
building and agenda setting process of the state. They would internalise the
“have-nots” in the process by regulating media, opinion process and fantasise
the have-nots’ perception about the so called liberal states.
4)
The distinction between public and private
domain is artificial. These are maintained only to offer justification for
protection of private wealth. Otherwise, the distinction line between the
private and public is always blurred. While haves’ wealth is protected, state
frequently enters into individual’s private domain in the name of surveillance.
In the same way, individual rights are more vehemently pressed to reinforce an
individualism that would disrupt greater community solidarities and more
substantial progressive change.
Therefore,
instead of accepting the doctrine of rule-based decision making (legal
formalism) or the situation based decision making (legal realism), critical
legal thinkers of 1970s sought to establish a sort of “reasoned elaboration.”
The concept as explained Roberto Mangabeira Ugar, is that rules and situations
could constitute “prescriptive system” at best. Relying on the prescriptions,
the judges would uncover “justice” through reasoned analysis of policies and
principles of law without questioning the "basic institutional
arrangements of democracy and state.[14]
By not questioning the “basic institutional arrangements” reasoned elaboration
thesis would distance itself from the revolutionary zeal of radical Marxism. Reasoned
elaboration would thereby permit the use of democratic legal system as a
mechanism of social change. If not used in this way, laws would serve a
stagnant society inherently biased towards wealth and power.
Continuing Relevance of CLS
The CLS movement
substantially waned within a decade of its emergence. Yet the offshoots of CLS,
like the critical race theory, critical feminist theory now play a major role
in contemporary legal scholarship. An impressive stream of CLS-style
scholarship has also emerged in the last two decades in the areas of
international and comparative law. Most importantly, apart from the philosophic
particularities of CLS, the networking and activist elements in the movement
contributed towards a radical change in the U.S. Law School curricula and teaching-learning
methodology. While the inherently Marxist-Socialist tendencies of the CLS
movement have faded a bit, the “activist premise” of CLS remain viable. Encouraging
the legal academia to question the institutions and norms from a sceptic’s
point of view is no less important today. Thinking and acting from a critical
perspective could surely bring a positive change in the overall politico-legal
scenario. Such a passionate upbringing and gathering of a folk of critical
thinkers and activities would ultimately benefit the laws and legal
institutions in the days to come. Seen in this line, CLS’s is a very elementary
and simple task – questioning the status
quo and asking for a change.
[1]Gerard J. Clark,
‘A Conversation with Duncan Kennedy,’ The Advocate: The Suffolk University Law
School Journal 24, no. 2 (1994): 56.
[2]Roberto
Mangabeira Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, Harvard Law Review (1983), http://www.robertounger.com/en/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/the-critical-legal-studies-movement-another-time-a-greater-task.pdf
(Accessed on November 5, 2017)
[3] Legality, Scott J
Shapiro, Harvard University Press, 2011, pp.472 at p 241
[4]Leiter,
B. (2010). Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue? Legal Theory,
16(02), 111–133. http://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325210000121
9Accessed on November 4, 2017)
[5] Frederick
Schauer, Formalism, 97 Yale Law Journal, 509, 548 (1988) at p 511
[6]Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation: Federal
Courts and the Law, The University Center for Human
Values Series (1997) at p 25
[7]Legality, Scott J
Shapiro, Harvard University Press, 2011, at p 242
[8]Ronald Dworkin, “No
Right Answer?” in Law, Morality and
Society, 54-84 (Hacker and Raz, Eds), Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1977. For a
general discussion see - Brian Bix, Law,
Language, and Legal Determinacy Oxford, Clarendon Press (1995),
Chapter 5 (Ronald Dworkin’s Right Answer Thesis)
[9]See
also Joan I. Schw,
Oliver Wendell Holmes's "The Path of
the Law": Conflicting Views of the Legal World, The American Journal
of Legal History, Vol. 29, No. 3 (Jul., 1985), pp. 235-250 Oxford University
Press, Stable url: http://www.jstor.org/stable/844757 (Accessed on November 2,
2017)
[10]Oliver
Wendell Holmes, Jr., "The Path of the Law," 10 Harvard Law
Review 457 (1897), Available online: http://www.constitution.org/lrev/owh/path_law.htm (Accessed on November 1, 2017)
[11]Robert A. Shiner, "Legal Realism," in Robert Audi, ed., The
Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1995, p. 425
[12]Brian Leiter, Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is
the Issue?, University of Chicago Public Law & Legal Theory Working
Paper, No. 320 (2010) Available online: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1178&context=public_law_and_legal_theory(Accessed
on October 31, 2017)
[13] The basic tenets
of CLS in this part are summed up from one the pioneer of CLS at Harvard Law School
Professor Mark V. Tushnet’s chapter on “Critical Legal Theory” in Martin P. Golding & William A.
Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and
Legal Theory. Blackwell. Chapter 5 pp. 80--89 (2005) at 80 Available
online: http://www.doi.org/10.1111/b.9780631228325.2004.00007.x (Accessed on
October 28, 2017)
[14]Roberto Mangabeira Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, New York: Verso (2015).
No comments:
Post a Comment