M Jashim Ali Chowdhury
PhD Researcher (Parliament Studies),
King’s College London.
The vibe that the
Westminster type parliaments are declining was first aired by Lord Bryce in
1921. General conclusion of Bryce’s comparative study between the United
Kingdom, United States, French and Italian parliament was plain - legislative
bodies had declined in brilliance, acumen, importance and interest. This later
took a name – The Decline of Parliament Thesis (DPT). Westminster type
parliaments are particularly vulnerable to the powers of Cabinet so far as it
relates to the law making, financial management and policy making. Cabinet
dictatorship was further strengthened by the rise of polarized and cohesive
party system in the nineteenth century. Situation is even worse in
jurisdictions where the Prime Minister is placed far above his cohorts in the
Cabinet. Today, parliament barely controls the legislative proposals that come to
and passes through it. It has virtually no say over foreign affairs and
security issues. Financial accountability mechanisms are increasingly falling
upon non-parliamentary bodies like Comptroller and Auditors General,
Anti-Corruption Commission, Multinational Donors and Lending Agencies. Parliament’s
oversight tools like ministerial responsibility has fallen prey to cohesive and
clientelist political parties and their predetermined agendas. Even parliament’s
“mere deliberative” ordeal in state policy making is under challenge. Mass
media has overtaken the bulk of agenda-setting and discourse setting function
in political debate. Parliament merely follows the policy vibe created
somewhere else. Rise of local government autonomy and community-based interest
groups directly linked to the government have relieved the MPs from most of
their representative functions. So now, the question is - what remains for parliament
and what it stands for?
Fortunately, Anti-DPT
scholars like Lord Norton and others believe that parliament still has
potentials. DPT scholars over-emphasize the elitist and coercive aspect of
legislatures, they argue. To them, a Pluralist-Institutional perspective would
better justify parliament as an institution both of coercion and persuasion. Legislature
may coerce by its voting power. If not possible, it may persuade by its
debating power. Elitist and coercive perspectives highlight the larger hold of
the cabinet over parliament. Instead, a Pluralist-Institutional view would
explain why and how the structures (committees, speaker etc) and procedures
(rules of procedure etc) of parliament may affect what is brought forward by
the government. Institutional view has two dimensions – rational choice
institutionalism and historical institutionalism.
True it is,
government of a given time would seek to manipulate the parliamentary bodies
and procedure towards its own advantage. But the
rational-choice explanation of institutional change as expounded Douglas North
suggest that such changes would be attempted only when the price for it is
worth risking. For example, governments in Bangladesh would think thrice to
reintroduce the fourth or fifth amendment like system again. This will be
legally unsustainable and politically suicidal. The political price that might
need be paid here constitutes a strong deterrent for such attempted change.
Parliamentary system is therefore safe at least for the foreseeable future.
Again, could the
rulers of the time attempt to reduce the authority of the Speaker, for example,
substantially? From a historical institutional analysis, this is almost
impossible to do. Parliamentary norms, ideas and etiquette developed over
thousands of years of Westminster system militant against such retrogression.
Same would be the situation had the rulers wanted to abolish the committee
system, ministerial responsibility, parliamentary pre-approval of taxes and
revenues, etc. Historical ideas and norms developed through institutional
practice are impossible to amend unless a decisive wave of public support
brings an inevitable “constitutional moment” for the ruling class. Constitutional
moments are admittedly hard to come by.
The Institutional
view of parliament calls for a Pluralist appreciation of the role and place of
legislature in Westminster-style governments. To assert that the modern
parliaments are far from decline, Robert Packenham identified a total of eleven
functions of legislatures and tabled those functions into three
major-categories – first, legitimation (democratic legitimacy to the
governance), second, recruitment, socialization and training (creation of
future cabinet rank and file from the parliamentary backbenchers) and third,
decisional and influence functions (law making and oversight). Prior to
Peckenham, Walter Bagehot also outlined five functions: elective (choosing the
government); expressive (public perception of current issues); teaching
(letting the people know things that might otherwise left unknown); informing
(raising the grievances of the people); and lastly, the law making – the most
conspicuous one to us.
A combined reading
of Peckenham and Bagehot suggests that empirical study, appreciation and
measurement of the Inform, Training and Influence Roles of parliament side by
side with its Legislative and Elective Role might prove a practicable way to
locate modern parliaments’ position within the DPT v. anti-DPT discourse. If
the parliament’s apparent weaknesses in the legislative and oversight functions
are recoverable at least in some extent through its Inform, Training and
Influence Role, we might be able to make a case for giving parliament a chance in
the overall body politic.
The pluralist-institutional perspective
is further substantiated by a recently articulated “Expectation Gap” analysis in the UK. Flinders and Kelso from
United Kingdom argues that the declinist scholars unrealistically increase
public expectations by posturing parliament as an arch rival of the executive. It
fails to accept that parliamentary government was explicitly intended to
deliver ‘strong government’. Again, while
inflating public expectations, the declinist scholars fail to close the gap
from below - parliament’s actual capability to deliver the expectation. Declinist
scholars bypass the existence and capacity of ‘informal, but no less
important,’ intra-party and inter-party avenues of legislative oversight
through pre-legislative opinion building, cross party committee deliberation
and post legislative scrutiny, etc. If the top bar of expectation is pulled
down by accepting a comparatively limited role of parliament, and if the bottom
bar of actual capacity is pulled up by acknowledging some less visible
intra-party and inter-party control mechanisms, then the peoples’ ‘Expectations
Gap’ would have been narrower and parliaments could get the attention and
appreciation it deserves. Institutions thrive only when those are cared for and
appreciated.
No comments:
Post a Comment